Ergebnis für URL: http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading13
   This is chapter 6 of the [1]"The Phenomenon of Science" by [2]Valentin F. Turchin
     ____________________________________________________________________________

   Contents:
     * [3]ABOUT CONCEPTS AGAIN
     * [4]ATTRIBUTES AND RELATIONS
     * [5]ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC
     * [6]HEGEL'S DIALECTIC
     * [7]MATHEMATICAL LOGIC
     * [8]OBJECTS AND STATEMENTS
     * [9]LOGICAL CONNECTIVES
     * [10]PREDICATES
     * [11]QUANTIFIERS
     * [12]THE CONNECTIVE "SUCH THAT"
     * [13]THE PHYSICAL OBJECT AND THE LOGICAL OBJECT
     * [14]FUNCTIONS
     * [15]SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS
     * [16]LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE
   _________________________________________________________________________________

   CHAPTER SIX.
   LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

ABOUT CONCEPTS AGAIN

   LET US BEGIN with the most fundamental concept of logic, the concept of the
   "concept.'' In chapter 2 we gave a cybernetic definition of the concept in its
   Aristotelian version-as a set of situations at the input of a cybernetic system.
   To master a concept means to be able to recognize it, that is, to be able to
   determine whether or not any given situation belongs to the set that
   characterizes this concept. This definition applies equally to complex cybernetic
   systems of natural origin about whose organization we have only a general idea
   (for example: the brain of an animal) and to those relatively simple systems we
   ourselves create for applied and research purposes.

   In the first case we arrive at the conclusion, that the system recognizes a
   certain concept, by observing external manifestations of the system's activity.
   For example, when we see that a dog becomes happily excited when it hears its
   master's voice and responds in a completely different way to all other sounds we
   conclude that the dog has the concept of ''master's voice.'' This concept
   develops in the dog naturally, without any special effort by the experimenter. To
   determine the maximum capabilities of the dog brain the experimenter may create
   unusual conditions for the animal and watch its reaction. I. P. Pavlov and his
   school conducted many such experiments. If a dog is shown plywood circles and
   squares of different sizes and colors and is fed after the presentation of a
   circle and punished after the presentation of a square, the dog will learn to
   distinguish the circle and the square and will respond differently when these
   shapes are presented. Thus, the dog is capable of recognizing certain general
   (abstract) concepts-in this case the concepts of circle and square abstracted
   from the features of size and color. This means we must conclude that the dog
   possesses the abstract concepts of ''circle'' and "square".

   But no sooner do we say this than we begin to feel that perhaps this conclusion
   was too hasty. The statement that the dog can possess the concept of ''master's
   voice'' (referring, of course, to the voice of a specific person) can be accepted
   without reservation, but the statement that the concept of square is accessible
   to the dog seems true in one sense and not in another. We shall take note of this
   now and return to the question later. In the meantime let us examine the dog's
   mental capabilities by indicating the very simple concepts known to be
   inaccessible to the animal. Suppose that you show the dog a box divided into two
   parts, each of which contains several billard balls. You want to force the dog to
   distinguish the case where the number of balls in each part is equal from the
   case where the number of balls in the parts differs. It is a safe bet that no
   matter how much you feed the dog and no matter how much you beat it you will not
   achieve your purpose. The concept of different numbers is inaccessible to the
   dog.

   Cybernetic systems possessing the ability to recognize concepts are also created
   artificially. Their importance is steadily growing in connection with cybernetic
   science and production. The development of artificial recognition devices
   (discriminators) plays a crucial part in understanding the general principles and
   concrete mechanisms of the working of the brain. These devices serve as models
   with which people try to lift the veil from the process of thinking. The creation
   of an "artificial brain'' which performs, at least partially, the same functions
   as the natural brain provides indications of how to approach investigation of the
   activity of the natural brain. It is interesting that one of the first results of
   comparing artificial and natural recognition systems was the conclusion that
   natural systems are very narrowly goal-directed and specialized. Within their own
   specialization they reach a high level of refinement, but they are completely
   impotent when the problem goes beyond this framework. Recognizing a person by
   voice is an extremely difficult problem for artificial cybernetic devices, but
   the brain of a dog resolves it easily. At the same time the problem of comparing
   the number of billard balls, which is very simple for an artificial system, is
   beyond the ability of a dog.

   In chapter 2 we considered a cybernetic discriminator that was fed information by
   signals from light-sensitive receptors arranged on a screen. We called the
   situation, that is to say the aggregate of values of all signals from the
   receptors, the ''picture''; it coincides with the image on the screen with a
   precision down to semitones. This device (picture discriminator) will serve as an
   illustration in this chapter too.

ATTRIBUTES AND RELATIONS

   SO FAR, the examples of concepts we have given have fit within the definition of
   the concept as a set of situations. But as it turns out, this definition does not
   apply to every concept that seems intuitively clear to us and manifests itself in
   language. For example' let us take the concept expressed by the prepositions
   ''inside'' or ''in.'' For those who do not like to see a concept expressed by a
   preposition, we can express it by phrases such as "to be located inside" or
   "location in". This concept is applicable to a device to whose input ''pictures''
   are fed.

   [IMG.FIG6.1.GIF]

   In figure 6.1 for example, spot A is inside contour B. But can we correlate the
   concept of ''inside'' to some definite set of pictures? No, we cannot. This can
   be seen, for example, from consideration of the picture shown in figure 6.2.

   [IMG.FIG6.2.GIF]

   In figure 6.2 a spot A is inside contour B, but not inside contour C. In figure
   6.2 b, spot A is outside contour B while spot C is inside it.

   Could these pictures be classed with a set of situations for "inside" which we
   would have to construct? Any answer will be unsatisfactory and arbitrary, because
   the question itself is meaningless. The concept of ''inside'' does not
   characterize a picture (situation) as a whole but rather the relation between two
   definite objects. details in the picture. As long as these objects are not
   indicated, a definite spot and a definite contour, it is meaningless to ask the
   question ''inside or not'''?

ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC

   WE SHALL call the concepts that express attributes of the situation as a whole
   ''Aristotelian,'' because Aristotle's logic is simply a consistent theory of the
   correct use of such concepts. For each Aristotelian concept there is a definite
   corresponding set of situations, specifically those situations in which the
   attribute expressed by this concept occurs. Therefore the Aristotelian concept
   can also be described as a certain set or class of situations (phenomena, objects
   in that extremely general sense in which these terms are used here; they are all
   equivalent to one another and to the term ''something'' [in Russian nechto] which
   is the most precise but also the most inconvenient because of the difficulties
   with Russian grammar its use entails). Therefore all the laws of Aristotelian
   logic can also easily be derived from the simplest properties of operations on
   sets.

   For example, let us take the classical syllogism:
   All men are mortal
       Socrates is a man
       _______________________

       Therefore Socrates is mortal.

   Three Aristotelian concepts participate in this reasoning: ''man,'' ''mortal,''
   and ''Socrates.'' The concept of ''man'' is characterized by the set of
   situations in which we say, ''This is a man.'' The same thing applies to the
   other concepts. To make the properties of the sets graphically clear let us
   represent each situation as a point within a certain square, as is shown in
   figure 6.3.

   [IMG.FIG6.3.GIF]

   Then this square will embody the set of all conceivable situations corresponding
   to the maximally general concept ''something.'' The other concepts, to which
   deterrent sets of points correspond, will be shown by different areas inside the
   square. The statement that ''all men are mortal,'' in other words ''every man is
   mortal," signifies that every point included in the area of ''man'' is also
   within the area of ''mortal'' (''mortal being''), which is to say that the
   ''man'' area is entirely inside the ''mortal'' area. In exactly the same way the
   second premise of the syllogism means that the ''Socrates'' area is entirely
   inside the ''man'' area. It follows from this that the ''Socrates'' area is
   within the ''mortal'' area, or in other words the statement "Socrates is mortal''
   is true.

   Figure 6.4 demonstrates the correctness of the following deduction rule
   (''disamis'' in logical terminology):

   [IMG.FIG6.4.GIF]
   All A are B
       Some A are C
       _______________________

       Therefore, some B are C.

   Aristotle's logic played an important role in the development of European
   culture. But it does not go deeply enough into the structure of our thinking: it
   is not able to reflect the process of breaking situations up into distinct parts
   (objects) and investigating the relations among these parts. In discussing the
   attributes of objects Aristotelian logic is completely adequate, because an
   isolated object can be pictured as a certain situation.

   Forming the set of such situation-objects, we obtain an abstract concept that
   expresses one of the properties of the object. Things are different with
   relations. Aristotelian logic can express the concept of the aggregate of objects
   which are in a given relation, but it has no means for expressing the concept of
   the relation as such. We can represent a set of pictures that have the form of
   contours with spots in the middle; this set generates the Aristotelian concept
   (attribute) of ''being" a contour with a spot in the middle.'' But there is no
   Aristotelian concept for ''being inside.'' Aristotle's logic is too global and
   superficial.

   Let us take the following deduction:
   Ivan is Peter's brother
       _______________________

       Therefore, Peter is Ivan's brother.

   The inference is correct, but to substantiate it one must state openly the
   premise which is taken for granted here: that the relation of ''brothers'' is
   symmetrical. This premise can be expressed by the phrase: ''If x is the brother
   of y, then y is the brother of x ".

   In this the letters x and y, represent any persons of the male sex. But this
   symbolism goes beyond the limits of Aristotelian logic.

   Can this syllogism be expressed in the language of Aristotle's logic? It can if
   we consider not individual people but pairs of people-or, more exactly, ordered
   pairs, which is to say pairs where one person is assigned the number one and the
   other receives the number two. Here is this syllogism, which is completely proper
   from the point of view of Aristotelian logic.
   The pair (Ivan and Peter) possesses the attribute: the first is the brother of
       the second
       Each pair possessing the attribute: ''the first is the brother of the
       second'' possesses the attribute: ''the second is the brother of the first''
       _______________________

       Therefore the pair (Ivan and Peter) has the attribute: "the second is the
       brother of the first.''

   Even though formally it is the same reasoning used before, this clumsy syllogism
   misses the mark because it does not reflect the main element in our initial
   syllogism, the symmetry in the relation of ''brothers.'' The attributes ''the
   first is the brother of the second'' and ''the second is the brother of the
   first'' are in no way broken down, in no way connected with one another, and in
   no way connected with the fact that they are applied to objects which have the
   appearance of an ordered pair.

   It was not accidental that we began our cybernetic investigation of concepts from
   Aristotelian concepts. They are simpler because they permit definition
   exclusively in terms of input and output states without referring to the internal
   structure of the recognition system. The same thing occurred in the history of
   human thought. People first became aware of the existence of Aristotelian
   concepts: awareness of relations came only much later.

   Because the chief thing in mathematics is to investigate relations among objects,
   Aristotelian logic is completely inadequate for expressing mathematical proofs.
   This was noted long ago; the examples from mathematics which traditional logic
   uses speak for themselves: they are extremely primitive and uninteresting. Until
   the very end of the nineteenth century, when a new (''mathematical'') logic began
   to be created, mathematics and logic developed independently of one another.

HEGEL'S DIALECTIC

   IN PHILOSOPHY Hegel delivered the decisive blow against Aristotelian logic. With
   his dialectic he showed that the world must be viewed not as an aggregate of
   objects that possess certain attributes, but rather as an aggregate of objects
   that stand in certain relations to one another. This does not exclude attributes
   from consideration, of course, for the concept of the relation is much broader
   than the concept of the attribute.

   A relation may be defined for any number of objects. Specifically, the number of
   objects may be one; such a relation is an attribute, a property. Pair relations,
   that is to say relations between two objects, are the clearest intuitively and at
   the same time the most important. Two is the minimum number of objects for which
   the relation ceases to be an attribute, and becomes a relation proper. The number
   two lies at the foundation of the Hegelian method, which is reflected in the very
   term ''dialectic".

   The most important features of Hegel's dialectic follow directly from the
   description of phenomena in terms of relations, not attributes. Above all, what
   follows from this approach is the theory of the interaction and interrelatedness
   of everything that exists. Further: If two elements are in correspondence and do
   not contradict one another, they act as something whole and their common
   attributes become paramount while the interaction, the relation, between them
   withdraws to a secondary position. Relations among elements. objects, manifest
   themselves to the extent that they are relations of opposition, contradiction,
   and antagonism. Thus, the idea of the struggle of opposites plays an important
   part in Hegel.

   When considering the relation between the state of an object at a given moment
   and the state of this same object at some other moment in time we come to the
   concept of change. Change is the relation between objects separated by a time
   interval. In the language that operates with attributes but not with relations.
   change cannot be expressed. The most that such language is capable of is
   depicting a series of states of the object which are in no way interconnected.

   Zeno's aporia concerning the arrow in flight is a brilliant expression of this
   inability. Let us consider the arrow in flight. Take a certain moment in time. At
   this moment the arrow occupies a definite position in space. Take another moment.
   The arrow again occupies a completely determinate position in space. The same
   thing is true for any other moment. This means that the arrow always occupies a
   definite position in space. This means that it is standing in place. In
   Aristotelian concepts the world is represented as something static, frozen, or at
   best mechanically duplicated with certain variations. On the other hand, having
   made the investigation of relations its object, the dialectic studies things from
   the point of view of their change. movement, and development. It discloses the
   historical causality and relativity (from the word ''relation''!) of things which
   are represented as unconditional and external when described in Aristotelian
   concepts. Combining the concept of opposition with the concept of the relation
   among states at successive moments in time generates the concept of the negation
   and the concept of the negation of the negation. The dialectic is dynamic and
   revolutionary.

   In relation to Aristotelian logic, Hegel's dialectic acted as a destructive
   force-and not just because of its ''general'' revolutionary nature but also
   because it pointed out the many contradictions that arise when a description of
   phenomena which demands the language of relations is squeezed into the narrow
   framework of the language of attributes. In Hegel and his followers these
   contradictions were often surrounded with a certain exalted aura and, one might
   say, a semimystical significance. This reflected, on the one hand. the idealistic
   orientation of Hegel's philosophy, and on the other hand a general characteristic
   of new doctrines, theories, and movements: in the initial stages of their
   development, trying to liberate themselves from the old intellectual framework,
   they prefer a paradoxical, exaggerated form and become heroic and romantic.
   Hegel's dialectic is the heroic epoch of the new logic, when the old logical
   formalism had been broken but the new one was not yet created. Therefore things
   seemed contradictory and not subject to formalisation (''dialectical'') which
   later proved to be beautifully ordered and formalized. To modern thinking, which
   makes free use of the language of relations and is armed with analysis of logical
   concepts and constructions, the He~elian style of thinking appears as obscure
   philosophizing about things which are clear. The following reasoning is a crudely
   simplified, caricature-like sketch of the Hegelian dialectical contradiction,
   showing the source from which this contradiction arises.

   ''Let us put the question: is the number 1,000 large or small? It is large
   because it is much more than one. It is small because it is much less than 1
   million. This means that it is both large and small at the same time. A
   dialectical contradiction. What is large is at the same time not large, A is
   not-A.''

   The concepts of ''large'' and ''small" were considered here as attributes of
   objects (numbers). In fact these are not attributes but concealed (by means of
   the grammatical category of the adjective) relations. An exact meaning can be
   given only to the concepts "larger'' and ''smaller.'' If we analyze the reasoning
   given above from this point of view it will prove to be simply nonsense. This
   caricature was not directed against Hegel (the credit due him for creating the
   new logic is indisputable) but rather against those who take an uncritical
   attitude toward Hegel's dialectical method and, in the second half of the
   twentieth century, propagate the style of thinking of the first half of the
   nineteenth century, ignoring the enormous progress made by logic in this century
   and a half.

MATHEMATICAL LOGIC

   THE DECISIVE FACTOR in the advance of logic was the development of mathematical
   logic in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. This process was
   generated by the needs of mathematics and was carried out by mathematicians. The
   gap between mathematics and logic was finally overcome. Having expanded its
   language and made it mathematical. Logic became suitable for describing and
   investigating mathematical proof. On the other hand, mathematical methods began
   to be used to solve logical problems.

   Having gained a base of operations in the field of mathematics, the new logic
   began to penetrate the natural sciences and philosophy. In this process the role
   of the mathematical element proper (the use of mathematical methods) declined.
   Nonetheless all modern logic is often called ''mathematical'' because of its
   language and origin.

OBJECTS AND STATEMENTS

   BEFORE GOING on in our analysis of language and thinking we need to give a short
   sketch of modern logic and those concepts which are related to language. For now
   we will leave the concepts related to the logical deduction (proof) aside.

   Modern logic divides everything that exists into objects and statements. In
   natural language statements are represented by sentences or groups of sentences
   and objects are depicted by words or combinations of words which make up the
   sentences. Examples of objects are ''heron,'' ''Uncle Kolya," or ''kolkhoz
   chairman.'' Examples of statements are: ''The heron died,'' or ''Uncle Kolya was
   elected chairman of the kolkhoz.'' Objects are most often expressed by nouns, but
   this is not mandatory. For example, in the statement ''To smoke is harmful,''
   ''to smoke'' is the object. In application to mathematics objects are usually
   called terms and statements are called relations. Examples of terms are:

   (1) 3.14;

   (2) ax^2 + bx + c;

   (3) [Integral.gif] f(z)dz.

   Examples of relations are:

   (1) ax^2 + bx + c = 0;

   (2) 0 < z  1 may be, a simple number p will be found
   which is a divisor of number n;

   (4) the sum of the squares of the legs of a right triangle is equal to the square
   of the hypotenuse.

   In logic the concepts ''object'' and ''statement'' are considered primary,
   intuitively clear, and indefinable. The formal difference between them is that a
   statement may be said to be true or false. Thus, the examples (3) and (4) of
   mathematical relations above are true, while the first and second may be true or
   false depending on the values of the variables x and z. The concepts of truth and
   falsehood are not applicable to objects.

   In logic objects and statements, which are considered elementary-meaning that
   they cannot be broken down into distinct constituent parts-are represented by
   letters. Objects are usually represented by small letters and statements by
   capital letters. We shall follow this system but we shall introduce one more
   convention. For clarity in writing and to reduce the number of verbal
   explanations we shall sometimes designate elementary objects and statements with
   words and phrases within quotation marks. Therefore phrases in quotes will be
   considered equal to letters.

   Objects and statements which are not elementary are obviously constructed from
   other objects and statements. We must now point out the methods of construction.
   Where there are two types of elements (objects and statements) and assuming that
   the elements serving as building material all belong to one type, we find that
   there are four possible types of constructions. We have reduced them to the
   following table.

   What Is Constructed What It Is
   Constructed From Name of the Construction
   Statement Statements Logical Connective
   Statement Objects Predicate
   Object Statements --
   Object Objects Function

LOGICAL CONNECTIVES

   THERE ARE FIVE widely used logical connectives. Negation (depicted by the symbol
   -), conjunction (sign &), disjunction (sign V), material implication (sign =>),
   and equivalence (sign ).

   The statement -A (read ''not A'') means that statement A is false. In other
   words, -A is true when A is false and it is false when A is true. The statement A
   & B (read ''A and B'') signifies the assertion that both A and B are true. It is
   true only if both statement A and statement B are true.

   The statement A V B ("A or B" ) is true if at least one of the two statements A
   and B is true.

   The statement A => B is read ''A entails B'' or "if A then B.'' This is untrue if
   A is true and B is false but is considered true in all other cases.

   Finally, the statement A  B is true if statements A and B are either both true
   or both false.

   Parentheses are used to designate the structure of connections, similar to the
   way they are used in algebra to designate the order of performance of arithmetic
   operations. For example, the statement -A & B means "S is untrue but B is
   true,"while the statement - (A & B ) means ''it is untrue that both A and B are
   true.'' And, just as in algebra, an order of seniority among connectives by the
   tightness of the bond is established to reduce the number of parentheses. Above
   we listed the connectives in order of decreasing tightness. For example, the
   conjunction is a tighter bond than implication and therefore the statement A => B
   & C is understood as A => (B & C). not as (A => B) & C. This corresponds to
   algebra where A + B x C is the same as A + (B x C), but not the same as (A + B) x
   C.

   Let us give a few examples of composite statements. A common Russian
   tongue-twister is ''The heron withered, the heron dried, the heron died'' [in
   Russian, ''tsaplya chakhla, tsaplya sokhla, tsaplya sdokhla'']. This statement
   may be written as follows: ''The heron withered'' & ''the heron dried'' & ''the
   heron died". The relation 00'' & ''Z< 1,'' while the
   relation |Z| > 1 is the disjunction ''Z> 1"V''Z (A B)]

   We will let the reader translate the following statement into conventional
   language: ''The light is turned on'' & ''the bulb is not burning'' => ''there is
   no electricity" V ''the plugs have burned out'' V ''the bulb is burned out.'' If
   we consider that statements can only be true or false, and consider nothing else
   about them, then the connectives we have listed are enough to express all
   conceivable constructions made of statements. Even two connectives are
   adequate-for example, negation and conjunction or negation and disjunction. This
   situation obtains, in particular, in relation to mathematical statements.
   Therefore other connectives are not used in mathematical logic.

   But natural language reflects a greater diversity in the evaluation of statements
   than simply separating them into true statements and false. For example, a
   statement may be considered meaningless or implausible even though it is possible
   ("There are probably wolves in this forest''). Special branches of logic which
   introduce other connectives are devoted to these matters. For modern science
   (unlike classical mathematical logic) these branches are not very important and
   we shall not deal with them.

PREDICATES

   A CONSTRUCTION that associates a statement with certain objects is called a
   predicate. Predicates are divided into one-place, two-place, three-place, and so
   on according to the number of objects they require. Functional notation is used
   to represent them. The predicate can be written as a function with unfilled
   places for variables, for example:

   P( ),

   L(, ),

   I( , , )

   or in the form

   P(x),

   L(x, y),

   I(x, y, z)

   having stipulated that x, y and z are object variables, that is, symbols which
   must in the last analysis be replaced by objects-although which objects is not
   yet known. But the second form of notation, strictly speaking, no longer
   represents a predicate; rather, it is a statement containing object variables. In
   addition to capital letters we shall also use words and phrases within quotation
   marks, for example: ''red'' (x) or ''between" (x, y, z) and special mathematical
   signs such as < (x, y).

   The one-place predicate expresses an attribute of an object while a predicate
   with more than one variable expresses a relation among objects. If the places for
   variables in the predicate are filled then we are dealing with a statement which
   asserts the existence of the given attribute or relation. The statement ''red''
   (''ball") means that the ''ball'' possesses the attribute ''red.'' The
   construction < (a,b) is equivalent to the relation (inequality) a < b. By joining
   predicate constructions with logical connectives we obtain more complex
   statements. For example we formerly wrote the |Z| > 1 without breaking the
   statement down into elements, but now we write it

                               > (z, "1" )V < (z, "-1" )

QUANTIFIERS

   IN MATHEMATICS a large role is played by assertions of the universality of a
   given attribute and of the existence of at least one object that possesses the
   given attribute. To record these assertions the following so-called quantifiers
   are introduced: universal quantifiers [forall.GIF] and the existential quantifier
   [exists.GIF] . Let us suppose that a certain statement S contains a variable
   (indeterminate object x, therefore we shall write it in the form S(x). Then the
   statement ( [forall.GIF] x)S(x) means that S(x) occurs for all x, while the
   statement ( [exists.GIF] x)S(x) represents the assertion that there exists at
   least one object x for which the statement S(x) is true.

   A variable included in a statement under the sign of a quantifier is called a
   bound variable, because the statement does not depend on this variable just as
   the sum

   Sum (i=n to m) S[i]

   does not depend on the indexes i. The bound variable may be replaced by any other
   letter that does not coincide with the remaining variables and the meaning of the
   statement will not change as a result. A variable which is not bound is called
   free. The statement depends entirely on the free variables it contains.

   Here are some examples of statements containing quantifiers.

   1) ( [forall.GIF] x) ( [forall.GIF] y) [''brother'' (x, y ) & ''man'' (y) =>
   ''brother'' (y, x)].

   For every x and every y, if x is the brother of y and y is a man then y is the
   brother of x.

   2) If D(x, y) is used to represent the statement ''x is a divisor of y,'' then
   one of the relationships cited above as an example of a statement will be
   represented in the form

   ( [forall.GIF] n)[>(n[1]"1" ) => ( [exists.GIF] p)D(P[1] n)]

   (( [exists.GIF] x) W (x) =>-( [forall.GIF] x)-W(x)

   The last relation is true for any statement W(x) and shows that there is a
   connection between the universal and existential quantifiers. From the existence
   of object x for which W(x) is true it follows that the assertion that ''W(x) is
   untrue for all x" is not true.

   A quantifier is also, in essence, a logical connective. The attribution of a
   quantifier changes a statement into a new statement which contains one less free
   variable. The difference from the connectives we considered above is that one
   must indicate, in addition to the statement, the free variable that must be
   coupled. The coupling of a variable means that concrete objects will be put in
   its place. If the number of objects that can be substituted for the variable is
   finite then the quantifiers can be viewed simply as convenient abbreviations
   because they can be expressed by the logical connectives of conjunction and
   disjunction. Suppose variable x can assume ~l values, which we shall designate by
   the letters x[1], x[2], . . . , x[n]. Then the following equivalences will occur.

   ( [forall.GIF] n)W (x) W (x[1]) &W (x[2]) & . . . &W (x[n]),

   ( [exists.GIF] x) W (x) - W (x[1]) VW (x[2]) V . . . VW (x[n])

THE CONNECTIVE "SUCH THAT"

   THE THIRD LINE of our table describes a construction that correlates an object to
   a statement. In natural languages this construction is very widely used. When we
   say ''red ball,'' we have in mind an object "ball" which possesses the attribute
   ''red,'' that is, it is such that the statement ''red'' (''ball'') is true. We
   transfer the statement about the object to the adjective which modifies the noun
   by which we designate an object; in other cases this can be achieved by
   participles, participial constructions, and constructions with the connectives
   "which'' and "such that". If we carry this analysis further we shall find that
   the noun, like the adjective, indicates first of all a definite attribute or
   attributes of an object. Like the word ''red,'' the word ''ball'' depicts a
   certain class of objects and may be correlated to a one-place predicate, "is a
   ball'' (x), or simply "ball'' (x). Then ''red ball" is such an object that the
   statements ''ball'' (a) and ''red'' (a) are true; in other words, the statement
   ''ball'' (a) & "red" (a) is, true.

   Notice that there are three independent elements operating in the logical
   notation: the letter a and the objects ''ball'' and ''red,'' while in writing in
   natural language there continue to be just two, ''red'' and ''ball.'' But the
   letter a, which is introduced in logical notation to identify the given object
   and distinguish it from others (and which is called the identifier), does not
   completely disappear in natural notation. It has been transferred to the concept
   ''ball,'' changing it from an attribute to an object' Unlike the word ''red,''
   the word ''ball'' identifies; you can say, ''This is the ball we lost yesterday''
   or I have in mind the same ball I was talking about in the previous sentence".

   But what is an ''object''?

THE PHYSICAL OBJECT AND THE LOGICAL OBJECT

   EXPERIENCE TEACHES US that the world we live in is characterized by a certain
   stability and repetition (and also, of course, by constant movement and
   variation). Suppose we see a tree. We walk away from it and the image of the tree
   on the retina of our eye changes in relationship to our movements. This change
   follows a definite law which is very familiar to us from observation of other
   objects. But when we return to our former place the image becomes almost exactly
   the same as it was before. Then we say, ''This is the tree,'' having in mind not
   only the image of the tree-the mental photograph-at the given moment in time but
   also the situations at nearby moments. If we are talking about classifying
   distinct situations by themselves, without considering their relations to other
   situations, then there is no difference at all between the noun and the
   adjective; the concept ''ball,'' just like the concept ''red,'' is completely
   defined by indicating a certain set of situations, and the discriminator (natural
   or artificial) of these concepts need only be able to use the following sentences
   correctly: ''This is red,'' ''This is not red,'' "This is a ball," and ''This is
   not a ball.''

   It is different when we must classify time sequences of situations rather than
   separate situations; we shall represent them as if they were a movie film whose
   frames each depict the situation at a given moment. In the movie film ''ball'' is
   not simply a detail of the situation in one frame; it is a detail that recurs in
   many. The discriminator of the concept ''ball'' cannot simply say, ''Yes, my
   friends, this is a ball!'' It must identify the particular details in the frames,
   saying: ''Here is how the ball looks in frame no. 137; here is the same ball in
   frame no. 138; here it is again in frame no. 139; and here is what it looked like
   in frame no. 120,'' and so on. The detail of the situation which is called ''the
   same ball'' can change quite considerably because of change in the position of
   the eye relative to the ball or a change in the shape of the ball itself, but the
   ball itself is invariably and absolutely the same. This invariability reflects
   the relative and temporal invariability we find in reality. It is as if we were
   to draw a line in time connecting the details in the different frames of film and
   declare that everything on this line is ''the same'' object. It is this line, in
   combination with a certain set of attributes (characteristics), that forms the
   concept of the physical object.

   The logical concept of the object reflects a property of physical objects-they
   preserve their identity. The object of logic is simply an identifier. Sameness is
   its only attribute, as reflected in our imaginary connecting line. If there are
   several different classes of objects, then various types of identifiers are
   ordinarily used to denote the objects in different classes. For example, line
   segments will be represented by small letters, points by capital letters, angles
   by Greek letters, and so on. But more concrete attributes characteristic of
   objects are written in the form of distinct assertions which include the
   introduced designations. This makes it possible to get by without a construction
   involving the connective ''such that.'' It is true that at the very beginning of
   his famous treatise Eléments de mathematique Bourbaki introduces the designation
   [tau][x][A(x)] for a certain object which possesses attribute A(x), that is, such
   that A{[tau][x][A(x)]} is a true statement. After this, however, the designation
   disappears from his text. Thus a definite name for the construction that
   associates an object with a statement has not even been established and we are
   forced to leave a blank in our table. In the last analysis, a complete division
   of labor between identifiers and statements is more convenient.

   For example let us take the sentence: ''The reddish-brown dog of Lieutenant
   Pshebyssky's widow killed the stray cat.'' When written in the language of logic
   this sentence breaks down into several statements which are implicitly contained
   in it and expressed h! means of the grammatical category of attribution. They can
   be joined into one statement using the conjunction sign, but we can obtain a more
   conventional and readable notation if we simply write out all the assertions
   being made-each on a new line separated by commas instead of conjunction signs.
   Assuming that the meaning of the attributes and relations being introduced is
   clear from the context, we receive the following equivalent of the above
   sentence:
   "dog'' (a),
       "reddish-brown'' (a),
       "belongs'' (a, b),
       "widow'' (b, c),
       "Lieutenant Pshebyssky" (c),
       "killed'' (a, d),
       "cat'' (d),
       "stray'' (d).

FUNCTIONS

   IN THE EXAMPLE, the predicate, Lieutenant Pshebyssky (c), is the only one that is
   plainly not elementary. In the attribute ''to be Lieutenant Pshebyssky'' we
   distinguish two aspects: to have the rank of lieutenant and to have the surname
   Pshebyssky. That is why this predicate is expressed by two separate words. Of
   course, we could have put each of these words in the form of a distinct
   predicate, but the fact that ''lieutenant'' is the rank of object c and
   ''Pshebyssky'' is the surname of it would not have been reflected in this case,
   and therefore we considered such a separation meaningless.

   ''Surname'' and ''rank'' are examples of a function of one free variable of a
   construction that juxtaposes the object which is the meaning of the function to
   the object which is the free variable. The function is written, as customary in
   mathematics, ''surname" (x), "rank'' (x), and so on. If there are several free
   variables they are separated from one another by commas, after which we are
   dealing with the function of several variables. This construction associates an
   object-value with a set of object-variables (their order is important!). An
   example of a function of two free variables is ''the result of a game of chess''
   (x, y). Let us give examples of functions from mathematics. Functions of one free
   variable: sin (x), |x|; |functions of two variables: arithmetic operations which
   may be written + (x, y), [~] (x, y), and so on; the distance (A, B) between two
   points in space A and B; a function of three variables: the angle formed at point
   B by paths to points A and C: the designation < (A, B, C), abbreviated as < ABC.

   Not every object can be substituted into the given function as a free variable or
   variables. If object a is a reddish-brown dog, then obviously the construction
   "rank'' (a) is meaningless. The construction + (a, B) is also meaningless where a
   is a number and B is a point in space. The set of objects (or sets of groups of
   objects) that can be free variables of a function (or functions) is called its
   domain of definition. The domain of definition of the function ''rank'' (x) is
   formed by all those objects which are military servicemen. The objects which can
   be values of the given function form the set which is called the area of values
   of the function. The area of values of the function "rank'' (x) includes such
   objects as "ensign,'' "lieutenant,'' "major,'' and the like, but it cannot
   include ''3.14'' or ''reddish-brown dog.'' The function "rank" (x) ascribes a
   definite rank to each serviceman.

   When we deal with functions, one of the relations among objects, the relation of
   equality, becomes particularly important. It is essential for establishing
   correspondence between functional constructions and the names of objects from the
   area of values of the function. When singling out an equality from the mass of
   other relations, we preserve its conventional notation x = y instead of writing
   it in the form of a predicate = (x, y). The fact that object c has the surname
   ''Pshebyssky'' and the rank ''lieutenant'' will look as follows:

   (''surname'' (c)= "Pshebyssky'') &

   (''rank" (c)=''lieutenant'')

   The equality relation can be defined formally by the following four assertions.

   1. ( [forall.GIF] a) (a = a)

   2. ( [forall.GIF] a) ( [forall.GIF] b)[(a = b) => (b = a)]

   3. ( [forall.GIF] a) ( [forall.GIF] b) ( [forall.GIF] c)[(a = b) & (b = c) C (a =
   c)]

   4. ( [forall.GIF] a) ( [forall.GIF] b){[a = b] => [W(a) =W(b)]}

   The last assertion is true for any statement W(x) which depends on variable x. As
   an exercise we suggest that the reader translate these assertions into natural
   language.

   In one of the examples given above we introduced the predicate D(x,y), which has
   the meaning ''x is a divisor of y". The concept of divisibility is wholly
   determined by the operation (function) of multiplication: therefore the predicate
   D(x,y) can be expressed by the function x. The natural (that is, whole positive)
   number p is a divisor of the number n when and only when there exists a natural
   number m such that n =pxm. In the language of predicate calculus

   ( [forall.GIF] p) ( [forall.GIF] n)[(D(p[1]n)  ( [exists.GIF] m)[n =
   x(p[1]m)]}

   To each function from n free variables we may correlate an n + 1 = place
   predicate which expresses the relation where one (for example the last) free
   variable is the given function from the remaining variables. For example,
   corresponding to function x(x,y) is the predicate M(x, y, z), which yields a true
   statement if and only it z = x X y. In the general case, corresponding to the
   function F(x, y, . . .z) there is the predicate F(x, y, . . .z, u), which
   possesses the property:

   ( [forall.GIF] x) ( [forall.GIF] y) ... ( [forall.GIF] z) ( [forall.GIF] u) {F[x,
   y, . . . , z, u]  [f(x, y, ..., z) = u]}

   The predicate F in fact expresses the same concept as the function F. Any
   statement which contains functional symbols can be rewritten, using predicate
   symbols only and introducing a certain number of additional object variables.
   Thus neither of the constructions that generate new objects-the construction with
   the connective ''such that'' and the function-is essential in principle, and it
   is possible to get along without them. Unlike the construction ''such that,''
   however, functional symbols are very convenient and they are used extensively in
   logic.

SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS

   IN CONCLUDING our short sketch of logic we shall consider the question of the
   relation between the language of logic and natural language. In the course of our
   discussion the important concepts of the syntax and semantics of language will be
   introduced.

   Let us recall the sentence about the reddish-brown dog, which we expanded into a
   set of statements expressed by means of predicates. The meaning of this set
   coincides with the meaning of the initial sentence, but the form of notation, the
   structure of the text, differs fundamentally. In semiotics (the science that
   studies sign systems) the aggregate of rules of construction of language elements
   is called its syntax and the relationship between language elements and their
   meanings is called semantics. Thus, the first thing that strikes one's eye in
   comparing logical and natural language is that the language of logic has a
   different syntax-one that is simple and uniform. It is based on the style of
   notation which has taken shape in mathematics; the construction of more complex
   language elements from simpler ones is represented by analogy with mathematical
   notation of operations and functions. The syntax of the language of logic is
   completely formalized, that is, there is a set of precisely formulated rules with
   which one can construct any language element. Moreover, no matter what correctly
   constructed language element (object or statement) we may take it will always be
   possible to re-create the element's construction. This process is called
   syntactical analysis of the element. It is easy to see that syntactical analysis
   is extremely simple and unambiguous in the language of logic.

   The syntax (in the semiotic sense) of natural language is its grammar-that is,
   the rules by which sentences are constructed from words (syntax in the narrow,
   linguistic sense of the word) and the rules for constructing words from letters
   (morphology). Unlike the language of logic, the syntax of natural language is far
   from completely formalized. It includes an enormous number of rules with an
   enormous number of exceptions. This difference is entirely understandable. The
   language of logic was created artificially, while natural language is a result of
   long development which no one controlled consciously, in which no preconceived
   plan was used. The grammar of natural language has not been constructed or
   designed; it is an investigation of an already complete system. an attempt to
   discover and formulate as clearly as possible those rules which speakers of the
   language use unconsciously.

   Syntactical analysis of the sentences of natural language often requires
   reference to semantics, for without considering the meaning of a sentence it will
   be ambiguous. For example, let us take the sentence: ''Here are the lists of
   students that passed the physics exam. In this sentence the attribute ''that
   passed the physics exam'' refers to students. If we use parentheses to make the
   syntactical structure of the sentence more precise, as is done in writing
   algebraic and logical expressions, they would be placed as follows: ''Here are
   the lists of (students that . . . passed).'' Now let us take the following
   sentence: ''Here are the lists of students that were lying on the dean's shelf.
   Formally the structure of this sentence is exactly the same as in the preceding
   one. But in fact a different placement of parentheses is assumed here,
   specifically: ''Here are the (lists of students) that . . . were lying.'' When we
   arrange parentheses in this way mentally we are relying exclusively on the
   meaning of the sentence, for we assume that students could not be lying on the
   dean's shelf.

   In general, constructions with the word ''that'' [Russian kotoryi] are very
   treacherous. In his book Slovo o slovakh [A Word about Words], L. Uspensky tells
   how he once saw the following announcement:

   CITIZENS-TURN IN SCRAP MATERIAL TO THE YARDKEEPER THAT IS LYING AROUND!

   It is not surprising that this construction did not find a place in mathematical
   logic!

LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

   THUS, to make a logical analysis-to construct the logical equivalent of a
   sentence in natural language. we must first of all make a syntactical analysis of
   the sentence; the results of the analysis will be reflected directly in the
   syntactical structure of the logical expression. But semantics is by no means
   left out either. When we say that "reddish-brown' is a one-place predicate,
   ''killed'' is a two-place predicate, ''distance'' is a function, ''and" is a
   logical connective, ''all'' is a quantifier, and so on, we are performing a
   semantic analysis of the concepts expressed in natural language. We classify
   concepts in accordance with a scheme fixed in the language of logic and we
   establish relations among the concepts. Logical analysis is essentially semantic
   analysis. Syntactical analysis is necessary to the extent that it is needed for
   semantic analysis.

   Logical analysis may be more or less deep. In our example it is very superficial.
   Let us see if we could continue it. and if so how.

   The concepts of ''dog," ''reddish-brown" and "cat'' are one place predicates,
   obviously elementary and not subject to further analysis. These are simple
   Aristotelian concepts which rely directly on sensory experience; every normal
   person is able to recognize them and the only way to explain what a ''cat'' is to
   point one out.

   The concept ''stray'' is also a one-place predicate, although a more complex one.
   If we were reasoning in a formal grammatical manner we could conclude that
   "stray'' means "that which strays.'' But this would be an incorrect conclusion
   because the verb to stray does not designate a length of time. A perfectly
   well-bred house cat may go out for an hour and stray across a roof, but this does
   not give anyone the right to call it a ''stray.'' It would be more correct to
   define a stray cat as a cat that has no master or, using a relation which is
   already included in our logical expression, as a cat that does not belong to
   anyone. Here is a formal notation of this definition:

   ''stray'' (x)  - ( [exists.GIF] y) ["belongs'' (x,y)]

   (It is assumed here that x is an arbitrary object.)

   Let us look at the relation ''belongs.'' In a certain sense we sneaked it in
   because the word ''belong'' was not in the initial sentence. But it was
   understood and semantic analysis revealed it! In the Russian sentence the
   relation of belonging was conveyed by the genitive case. Here we see a clear
   example of the ambiguity and inadequacy of syntactical analysis. We used the
   genitive case in the constructions ''the widow's dog ''the dog of the widow'']
   and "the dog's mistress'' but in no way can it be said that the mistress belongs
   to her dog. The construction ''the widow's nose'' can of course be interpreted as
   the ''nose that belongs to the widow.'' But here we are already encountering the
   semantic ambiguity of the word ''belong,'' for it is obvious that the nose
   belongs to the widow in a different way than the dog belongs to her.

   It requires a good deal of work to break the concept "belong" into its elementary
   constituent parts; this would require a description of the customs and laws
   related to the right of ownership. Only in this case can the meaning of
   ''belong'' be explained. The predicate "widow" and the functions "rank'' and
   ''surname'' (which we introduced during our analysis of the concept ''Lieutenant
   Pshebyssky'') are also bound up with the social sphere and require further
   analysis. Finally the concept "killed'' although it is not linked with the social
   sphere and is plainly simpler (closer to sensory experience) than the preceding
   concepts would also have to be subjected to logical analysis. In this analysis it
   would be possible to identify. first of all the element of completion in the
   action. which is expressed by the Russian verb form secondly the final result
   (the death of the victim) and thirdly the typical characteristic of the action
   expressed by the Russian verb zagryzt' ]-use of the teeth.

   Logical analysis of language is an extremely interesting line of investigation,
   but we cannot dwell on it here. Those who are interested are referred to Elements
   of Symbolic Logic (New York: Free Press. 1966) by H. Reichenbach one of the
   founders of this field.

   Let us summarize the results of our comparison between natural language and the
   language of logic. The language of logic has a simple and completely formalized
   syntax. By syntactical and semantic analysis a text in natural language can be
   translated to the language of logic-that is, it can be correlated with a text in
   the language of logic that has the same meaning. Semantic analysis of the natural
   text during translation may be more or less deep which is to say that the
   predicates and functions included in the logical text may be closer or further
   from immediate sensory and emotional experience. There are predicates and
   functions which cannot be broken down into more elementary constituents and which
   therefore cannot be defined in any way except by reference to experience. We
   shall call such predicates and functions primary.
     ____________________________________________________________________________

References

   1. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/default.html
   2. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/turchin.html
   3. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading2
   4. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading3
   5. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading4
   6. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading5
   7. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading6
   8. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading7
   9. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading8
  10. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading9
  11. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading10
  12. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading11
  13. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading12
  14. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading13
  15. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading14
  16. http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/POS/Turchap6.html#Heading15


Usage: http://www.kk-software.de/kklynxview/get/URL
e.g. http://www.kk-software.de/kklynxview/get/http://www.kk-software.de
Errormessages are in German, sorry ;-)